Square root of 2 is irrational
The statement we are going to discuss and prove is known as Theorem of Theaetetus due to its appearance in Plato's Theaetetus dialog:
Theaetetus: Theodorus was proving to us a certain thing about square roots, I mean the square roots of three square feet and five square feet, namely, that these roots are not commensurable in length with the foot-length, and he proceeded in this way, taking each case in turn up to the root of seventeen square feet; at this point for some reason he stopped. Now it occurred to us, since the number of square roots appeared to be unlimited, to try to gather them into one class, by which we could henceforth describe all the roots.
Socrates: And did you find such a class?
Theaetetus: I think we did; but see if you agree.
Socrates: Speak on.
Theaetetus: We divided all numbers into two classes. The one, consisting of numbers that can be represented as the product of equal factors, we likened in shape to the square and called them square or equilateral numbers.Socrates: And properly so.
Theaetetus: The numbers between these, among which are three and five and all that cannot be represented as the product of equal factors, but only as the product of a greater by a less or a less by a greater, and are therefore contained by greater and less sides, we likened to oblong shape and called oblong numbers.Socrates: Excellent. And what after this?
Theaetetus: Such lines as form the sides of equilateral plane numbers we called lengths, and such as form the oblong numbers we called roots, because they are not commensurable with others in length, but only with the plane areas which they have the power to form. And similarly in the case of solids.Below we shall concentrate on the one root -- that of 2 -- that Theaetetus has not mentioned and at times suggest an extension to a more general result. But first let's see how Richard Dedekind, one of the people most responsible for the current definition and understanding of irrational numbers, treated Theorem of Theaetetus:
Proof 1
Let
... If there exists a rational number whose square is
and we may assume that
the number
which is contrary to the assumption respecting
Proof 2
A standard proof (e.g., [Rademacher and Toeplitz, Ch. 4]) of this result does not differ from the proof that
The premise
Proof 3
Following is another intuitive one [Laczkovich, p. 4, Davis & Hersh, p. 299]. This one is based on the assertion that every number is uniquely (up to the order of factors) representable as a product of primes. (A prime is a number divisible only by itself and
Proof 3'
Here's a modification that only counts the factors equal to
Proof 4
Following is yet another illuminating proof. As in the standard proof, assume
J. L. Lagrange in his Lectures on Elementary Mathematics (1898) argues that "... it's impossible to find a whole number which multiplied by itself will give
More than half a century earlier (1831), Augustus De Morgan explained that "...
The latter proof makes it entirely obvious that unless a square root of an integer is an integer itself, it is bound to be irrational. Furthermore, the same argument applies to roots other than square. Unless it's an integer itself, a fifth root of an integer is an irrational number!
The proofs above, directly or indirectly, appeal to the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic. In an article Irrationality Without Number Theory (Am. Math. Monthly, 1991), Richard
Beigel set out to check how much of Number Theory is actually needed. He showed that for any integer
Proof 5
Let
Richard's argument can be modified to invoke an infinite regression which is impossible for positive integers. Assuming
Proof 6
If
Proof 7
And here's another geometric proof I came across in an article by Tom Apostol (The American Mathematical Monthly, v 107, N 9, pp 841-842.) This one is so simple it may pass as a proof without words. But this is what his author had to say:
This note presents a remarkably simple proof of the irrationality of
By the Pythagorean theorem, an isosceles right triangle of edge-length
Construction. A circular arc with center at the uppermost vertex and radius equal to the vertical leg of the triangle intersects the hypotenuse at a point, from which a perpendicular to the hypotenuse is drawn to the horizontal leg. Each line segment in the diagram has integer length, and the three segments with double tick marks have equal lengths. (Two of them are tangents to the circle from the same point.) Therefore the smaller isosceles right triangle with hypotenuse on the horizontal base also has integer sides.
The reader can verify that similar arguments establish the irrationality of
Essentially the same diagram has been used in a Russian geometry textbook by A. P. Kiselev, p. 121. The book, first published in 1892, has been in a systematic use up to the late 1950s with practically no competition, and frequently in the ensuing years. A proof to the same effect but with a paper folding interpretation is due to [Conway and Guy, pp. 183-185]
[Rademacher and Toeplitz, Ch. 4] gave two proofs of the irrationality of
Proof 8
Assume [Laczkovich, Gardner] that
But this contradicts the minimality of q.
(Prof. Claus I. Doering, Instituto de Matemática - UFRGS, Brazil, has pointed to a much earlier reference. The proof appeared in a footnote of the classic A Course of Modern Analysis by E. T. Whittaker and G. N. Watson, 4th Edition, Cambridge University Press, 1927. The footnote had also been included in the 3rd edition (1920).)
Proof 8'
Obviously, the proof can be restated as
(Gary Davis has suggested an alternative formulation: If there is an integer
Proof 8''
A kindred proof has been published by Edwin Halfar (Am Math Monthly, Vol. 62, No. 6 (Jun-Jul 1955), p. 437). Suppose
In plain English this asserts that given two squares with integer sides and one having twice the area of the other, there exist a pair of smaller squares with the same properties.
Proof 8'''
A superb graphic illustration for the latter has been popularized by J. Conway around 1990, see [Hahn, ex. 37 for Ch. 1]. Conway discussed the proof at a Darwin Lecture at Cambridge. The lecture appears alongside other Darwin lectures in the book Power published by Cambridge University Press. Conway's contribution is included as the chapter titled "The Power of Mathematics". The text can be found online. Conway attributes the proof to the Princeton mathematician Stanley Tennenbaum (1927 - 2006) who made the discovery in the early 1950s while a student at the University of Chicago.
Given two squares with integer sides, one twice the other
move the smaller squares
into opposite corners of the bigger square
The intersection of the two forms a square at the center of the diagram. Their union leaves two squares at the free corners of the diagram. By the Carpets Theorem, the two areas are equal:
(Obviously, these squares also have integer sides.)
Proof 8IV
Another illustration by Grant Cairns appeared in Math. Mag. 85 (2012), p. 123:
The first two steps of the infinite discent
are suggestive of the continuation
There are extensions of the geometric arguments to regular polygons other than the square that illustrate the irrationality of
Proof 8V
Here's a variant from Am Math Monthly (120 (August/September) 2013, p 674) by Samuel G. Moreno and Esther M. García-Caballero:
If
so that
Proof 9
This proof is due to Alex Healy and was once available online at The Braden Files site. I owe the deepest thanks to Rick Mabry (Software Developer turned Professor) for pointing me in the right direction.)
Consider the set
(1)
Assume
(This proof has also appeared in an article Irrationality of Square Roots by P. Ungar, Math Magazine, v. 79, n. 2, April 2006, pp. 147-148, with an extension to roots of more general polynomials with integer coefficients, and [Laczkovich, pp. 4-5])
Proof 10
This proof too is by D. Kalman et al (Variations on an Irrational Theme-Geometry, Dynamics, Algebra, Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 70, No. 2 (Apr., 1997), pp. 93-104).
Let
By the definition,
Two facts are worth noting: (a) matrix
Since
Proof 11
Conway and Guy (pp. 184-185) argue that if
Assuming that
so that
This gives a simpler form for
Proof 11'
Geoffrey C. Berresford (Am Math Monthly, Vol. 115, No. 6 (June-July 2008), p. 524) offered a different route from the assumption
with
If two fractions are equal, with one in lowest terms, the numerator and denominator of the other are a common integer (say
(I am grateful to Prof. Claus I. Doering from Instituto de Matemática - UFRGS, Brazil for bringing this proof to my attention.)
Proof 12
Alan Cooper found what I would call a common-sense proof of the fact at hand. He based his proof on an observation that squaring a finite decimal fraction, say
In case where the fraction is not a finite decimal, we may switch to another number system in which the fraction is finite. The same argument now applies.
Alan notes that the above is a way of interpreting Proof 4.
Proof 13
Following Nick Lord (Math Gazette, v 91, n 521, July 2007, p. 256) we shall show that, for an integer
is never an integer. Indeed, if say
which would imply that
Assume then that
for coprime
is not an integer.
Proof 14
Gustave Robson (Am Math Monthly, Vol. 63, No. 4 (Apr., 1956), p. 247) published a short proof preceded by a remark: The following proof was invented by Robert James Gauntt, in 1952, while he was a freshman at Purdue. I was unable to induce him to write up his proof.)
Proof 14'
This proof is by Stuart Anderson.
In
(It can be shown that the equation
In general, it is easy to see that
Proof 14''
This proof was found by Sergey Markelov when yet in high school. In the decimal system, a square of an interger may only end in one of the following digits:
Proof 15
2-proofs-in-1 from The American Mathematical Monthly 114 (May 2007), p. 416. The proof is by Xinyun Zhu of Central Michigan University.
Starting as in the proof from Conway and Guy, let
Assume
for any
Since
From
which contradicts
which is an integer. A contradiction.
Proof 16
(N. C. Ferreño, Yet Another Proof of the Irrationality of
Consider a linear mapping
Since
In either case,
Proof 17
Yoram Sagher gave a modification of Dedekind's argument (Am Math Monthly, Vol. 95, No. 2. (Feb., 1988), p. 117):
Suppose
where the denominator is positive and smaller than the one in the original fraction. Continuing, we get an infinite decreasing sequence of positive integers, an impossibility.
This proof does not use any properties of primes and would thus be fully accessible to Pythagoras and to Theodorus.
Proof 17'
Following up on Y. Sagher proof, Robert W. Floyd published (Am Math Monthly, Vol. 96, No. 1 (Jan., 1989), p. 67) an extension:
Assuming Pythagoras understood Euclid's algorithm, the following proofs show how he could have demonstrated that any integer root of an integer is an irrational or an integer, and even that the cube root of an integer either is not the root of a quadratic (i.e., not in the form
I placed the proof into a separate file.
Proof 18
This is a proof by D. Kalman et al (Variations on an Irrational Theme-Geometry, Dynamics, Algebra, Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 70, No. 2 (Apr., 1997), pp. 93-104).
$
$
Observe that
Let
The following diagram only shows three equal segments that are important for the proof.
Assume
This proof too does not use any properties of primes and would thus be fully accessible to Pythagoras and to Theodorus.
The proof admits an algebraic equivalent. Suppose
Proof 19
I am grateful to Aharon Meyerowitz from Florida Atlantic University for bringing to my attention the geometric arguments from The Elements of Dynamic Symmetry by Jay Hambidge (the book is available online.)
Cut off of a
which shows that the standard "infinite descent" argument applies. Were
This argument may serve as an illustration to Proof 8.
The book contains another approach illustrated by the following diagram:
Here two
Proof 20
The irrationality of
Proof 21
Also
Proof 22
The irrationality of
Proof 23
A modified argument leads to a criterion of irrationality via a limit. I placed the proof on a separate page.
Proof 24
The concept of limit is central in the following proof that is based on solving a simple difference equation:
The details are on a separate page.
Proof 25
Samuel G. Moreno, Esther M. García-Caballero (The Mathematical Gazette, July 2013) derive the irrationality of
The details are in a separate file.
Proof 26
Samuel G. Moreno and Esther M. García-Caballero also proved irrationality of
Proof 27
Moreno and García-Caballero sent me an unpublished proof where they employed - in a playful manner - the well known formula for the sum of the first odd numbers
Proof 28
A purely number theoretical proof - the last for 2014, with a generalization to the irrationality of
Proof 29
A proof by M. Jacobson and H. Williams exploits the behavior of two sequences defined in terms of each other:
The details can be found in a separate file.
It's edifying to recall an estimate of approximation of irrational numbers with rational ones.
The irrationality of
In case you are curious,
Ludmila Duchêne and Agnès Leblanc put together an enchanting literary tribute to the question of irrationality of
References
- J-P Allouche & J. Shallit, Automatic Sequences, Cambridge University Press, 2003
- E. Barbin, The Meanings of Mathematical Proof, in In Eves' Circles, J.M.Anthony, ed., MAA, 1994
- J. H. Conway, R. K. Guy, The Book of Numbers, Copernicus, 1996
- P. J. Davis and R. Hersh, The Mathematical Experience, Houghton Mifflin Company, Boston, 1981
- J. W. R. Dedekind, On Irrational Numbers, in A Source Book in Mathematics by D. E. Smith, Dover, 1959, pp. 38-40
- A. De Morgan, On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics, Dover, 2005, p. 130
- M. Gardner, Gardner's Workout, A K Peters, 2001
- A. Hahn, Basic Calculus: From Archimedes to Newton to its Role in Science, Springer Verlag & Key College, 1998 (Also available online)
- M. Lasckovitch, Conjecture and Proof, MAA, 2001.
- H. Rademacher, O. Toeplitz, The Enjoment of Mathematics, Dover, 1990.
- S. K. Stein, Mathematics: The Man-Made Universe, 3rd edition, Dover, 2000.
- H. M. Stark, An Introduction to Number Theory, MIT Press, 1970
- I. Thomas, Greek Mathematical Works, v1, Harvard University Press, 2006
- D. Wells, You are a Mathematician, John Wiley & Sons, 1995
|Contact| |Front page| |Contents| |Impossible| |Up|
Copyright © 1996-2018 Alexander Bogomolny
68773619