Why macroeconomics is not
utilitarian
A distinction between
“utility” in philosophy and “utility” in economics
Matt Berkley
Draft, 16 June 2003
Introduction
There is in economics, and sometimes in moral philosophy, a confusion which is generally unacknowledged. A cross-sectional concept of “utility” is not a utilitarian concept.
Economists
often write of increasing utility
- better consequences for
people. The problem is that their
measures of welfare do not measure consequences for people, but are based on
the difference between welfare measures in living populations, whose members
change. Classical - Millian or Benthamite - utilitarianism
is concerned with the greatest good to the greatest number. Economic theorists write of maximising utility. They often use the word in a different
sense from that of Mill or Bentham.
This article does not tackle other assumptions in economics which are also open
to question:
a) the presumed linear relationship between [income] and [gains in purchasing
power], on which see my “Inflation and poverty”;
b) the presumed linear relationship between [gains in purchasing power] and [increases
in economic welfare], on which see “The Wealth of Persons”;
c) the presumed linear relationship between [increases in economic welfare] and
[increases in well-being], on which ditto.
This article is purely concerned with the conceptual structure of thinking
about welfare increases. With that in
mind, let us talk about income.
When a macroeconomist talks about raising average incomes, there is an
ambiguity. Do they mean raising the
population average, which will happen if poor people die earlier, or increasing
people’s average income? The second
of these is not knowable from the first.
There is an area of moral philosophy which is concerned with benefits to
future generations. But that is not
in any way relevant to the primary aim of social science, which is to make reliable
statements about trends - in the case of economists’ statements about
aggregate gains, about trends for real people during a period. I am not here talking about what is right
or wrong. I am talking about the conceptual
structure of a system of thought which claims to measure aggregate gains to
real people during a period. The
conceptual structure is not that of utilitarianism.
Average “utilitarianism”
is not utilitarian
Economics
is substantially[1] based, not
on Benthamite utilitarianism, but on what has been called, misleadingly,
“average utilitarianism”. There are
many views which have been called “average utilitarianism”[2]; I am referring to the view that the best
outcome results in the highest level of average welfare in a later
population [3].
The term “average utilitarianism” as applied to this view is misleading, because it uses a different definition of utility. Classical utilitarianism does not compare
states of affairs for the people who happen to be alive at different times,
as macroeconomics does, but
aggregates of consequences for all people affected.
Utilitarianism looks at all consequences even at the level of the individual. A statement that
“decision X in 1990 caused me to be happier in 2000”
is not logically equivalent to the statement
“decision X in 1990 caused me to be happier during the period 1990-2000”.
The
difference between these two statements, and the implications of this
difference, become clearer once we think about more than one person.
Utilitarianism is not
about states of affairs, but about consequences over time
Before going on to discuss this, I would like to comment on the phrase “states of affairs”. This phrase has been used by both the philosopher Bernard Williams and the economist Amartya Sen in discussing utilitarianism. I submit that the phrase is not clear enough for the purpose, and gives a misleading impression. It could be defined as equivalent to talking about histories or prospects for individuals. Either would make it fit utilitarianism, but the ordinary meaning of the phrase is not equivalent to those. I think it is clearer to stick to the word “consequences”. Otherwise, we may end up thinking about measuring static welfare levels of the living, which is not what utilitarianism is about.
A related problem concerns the use of the word “outcome”. The word, used in relation to
consequences, or utility, is ambiguous:
it can mean
a) overall consequences during a period
or during a lifetime,
or
b) the state of affairs at the end of a period.
In discussing “averagism” below, I mean “future averagism”, in the sense of “aiming for higher average welfare levels in a future population”. This sense might be made clearer by my using a phrase such as “leapfrog averagism”. Such a phrase would help to clarify that what I am referring to - average “utilitarianism” - is a view which leaves out some intermediate consequences in its overall assessment of goodness and badness.
Whatever words are used, they must be clear as to which of (a) or (b) above they refer to - the outcome over time, or the outcome by the end.
Here is why, in relation to the most influential practical use of consequentialist philosophy in the world today.
Macroeconomics compares
levels of welfare in two sets of people
- not the consequences for one
set
Any
moral or social-scientific outlook
which is concerned with the relative merits of later states of affairs among living people (for
example, average welfare at a later date) involves comparing welfare at two
times, using two sets of people -
a)
one set of people at the beginning of a period, and
b)
one set of people at the end.
This is the logico-mathematical structure
used by the “averagist” and the macroeconomist. In economics, it forms the entire basis of calculation of
“utility”. The fact that economists say their discipline has roots in Benthamism is irrelevant, because it
isn’t true. An appropriate analogy
would be that it has been grafted on.
The two sets of people may overlap or contain exactly the same members, but
their memberships are irrelevant to the averagist. In other words, it makes no difference to the averagist - a “future-state-of-affairs-ist”, such as
someone solely concerned with the state of the economy at a time in the
future - whether the people in the two sets are
a)
the same
people, or
b)
mostly the
same people, or
c)
different
people entirely.
If there is more income per capita in the second set of people (the later population) then that is what is important to the person studying the economy. Economics uses cross-sectional studies: studies involving sets of people alive at particular times. Economists study the economy as a theoretical entity, not the progress of individual people or aggregates of the progress of individuals. They infer income gains from opinions about the insignificance of demographic change as mathematical determinants of averages. Whether these opinions in any particular case bear any relation to the truth is unknown. In practice, the speculation is justified in countries where the economist knows that demography was stable, and less justified where they have less knowledge, or knowledge of demographic change, or both.
Utilitarianism looks at one set of people. In contrast to the macroeconomic approach,
utilitarianism with a direct line of descent from Bentham is a doctrine about consequences for one set of people -
the set of all people
affected by the events.
Writings about
“utility” in economics do not usually refer to the differences between the
logical structures of economics and classical utilitarianism:
1)
Economics uses
cross-sectional studies, as described above.
2) In contrast to Benthamite utilitarianism,
economics measures the duration of
a benefit differently for the
majority and the richer minority. If
the rich live longer, the average rises.
If the majority on below-mean incomes live longer, it falls. In
all countries, more people have below-mean incomes than above-mean
incomes.
3)
Economics uses
averages rather than totals as the basic method
of aggregation.
4)
In economics,
the result (aggregate “utility” as state of affairs in a later population) is
mathematically determined by changes
in demographic composition, as
well as individual welfare gains. Classical utilitarianism, on the other
hand, looks at everyone affected, so demographic change isn’t an issue [4].
Moral philosophers sometimes say that “average utilitarianism” gives the same
results as classical utilitarianism if the population size does not
change. This is a mistake. A further condition relates to who ends up in the later population.
This is partly about birth rates, but also about the ratio of well-off to badly-off people who survive the period.
If the well-off survive disproportionately, the average will rise, other things being equal. If
the less-well-off survive disproportionately, the average will fall, other things being equal. So
an additional condition is necessary for classical utilitarianism and averagism
to give the same results: the
condition is that there is insignificant demographic change.[5]
If people on
below-mean income [7] live longer,
then other things being equal, per capita income will be lower in the later population.
No-one’s income has fallen, but “per capita income” as an abstract
statistic has fallen. The statistic is essentially abstract,
because the concept of a population is abstract. The population of a
geographical area is not a real group of people over time -
just as there is no constant set of (other) chimpanzees in the
world. In Benthamite terms, though, what happens if someone in the
majority lives longer? Assuming for
the moment a perfect correlation between income and happiness -
there will be higher utility
- a greater good. The
macroeconomist will say that there is lower utility, because the
economist’s definition of utility is fundamentally different.
Logically, an
inference that
“people’s incomes went down on average by x%”
based purely on
comparing averages for the two
sets of people (earlier and later
populations)
is invalid, if there
is no information about demographic change.
In other words, if
you know that
people later were better
off on average than people before,
this doesn’t of
itself tell you that
“people did better on average”.
This is a more
subtle variant of the objection against averagism that if the best-off kill the
others, average welfare in the population afterwards will be higher.
At present, if a government
neglects the poor and extends the life length of the rich, and this makes per capita income 1% higher in the later
population, economists are allowed
by their training to state that “people’s
annual incomes rose by 1%” -
even if no-one’s annual income changed.
This is invalid,
but economists are allowed by their training to make these kinds of statements
for all geographical areas and all subsections of economies -
even those segments of the economy containing the most malnourished people
in the poorest country, and in situations where economists know least about
birth rates and survival rates.
The fundamentals of
welfare-economic theory about real people’s progress are based on the
implausible assumption of no
significant demographic change in
any population which economists have studied or will study in the future.
(Average rise or fall in income among real people) is a function of
(per capita income change) and (the impact of demographic change).
Where the impact of demographic change is unknown, the average
percentage gain or loss is unknown.
Here is the muddled state of economic thinking.
1) At present, if the poor live longer, and as a result average income is lower in the later population even though no-one’s income has fallen, the current, incomplete, form of the equation - and the theory and philosophy of economics, both of which fail to make the relevant distinction - allow an economist to say that “people’s incomes fell”.
2) Where the economist does not know whether the changes in the average were caused by demographic factors or income rises/falls, they are still allowed by their training to make a categorical statement as if they knew the average rise or fall.
This logical problem is the result of a confusion between classical utilitarianism and leapfrog averagism. Utilitarianism comes to conclusions about benefits to real people, but averagism comes to conclusions about statistics. The difference between average welfare among those at the start and those at the end does not even fundamentally tell us whether those alive at a the end did better or worse, let alone how much better or worse.
This is of direct
relevance to the interpretation of real-life macroeconomic studies claiming to
measure income gains. The logical
problems are more acute in relation to those studies claiming benefits or
losses from particular policies in different countries. The logical relationships in these studies
are more complex, because the studies involve comparisons of different
countries and time periods, but the principle is the same. Average gain is mathematically a function
of both income gains and demographic change.
In real countries, there are great differences in how long poor people
live. In some real countries, effective
health care services have had a great impact on longevity for poor people. In others, disease and malnutrition have
not been tackled so well. And yet in
the present logical structure of economics, other things being equal, the
survival of a poor person until the next time of measurement is necessarily
counted as a “disutility”.
The implication is
that some conclusions of economists, widely accepted, about what is good for
poor people are unfounded.
How far the speculative
nature of the assumptions about demography has made a practical difference in
real-life studies is not known.[8] For the purposes of assessing the validity
of some studies it is in practice impossible to find out in retrospect.
What is obvious is
that there is a serious theoretical problem.
The most striking examples are clear.
If average income went up after the plague because of deaths, then the
same may happen due to AIDS. An
assertion that “the plague benefited people on average” would be a different
statement. On the question of children,
it is obvious that the one-child policy in China will have made rises in per capita income larger than average income gains to real people.
Empirical research has confirmed the impact of this demographic
change on economic growth statistics, as it has in the case of the “East Asian
economic miracle” where a significant part of the rise in per capita income was
due to the proportion of children going down.
In addition, there
are some other facts about economic history which cannot be explained by the
conventional “zero effect of demographic change on average income” hypothesis,
but can be explained by a hypothesis that there are significant effects of
demographic change: countries where
people - mostly poor people - have made dramatic gains in life length but
average income is low.
It is plausible that
differences in life length between countries contribute significantly to
economic statistics.
What is certain is
that the present muddled logic of economics is open to severe abuse by
sophists. What is a sophist? Someone
who makes a fake point. A person
could say that people have done better when in fact they have done worse.
This conceptual structure is not adequate for thinking about past economic
gains to people (think of the plague, or the huge famines in China in the early
1960s) or for thinking about possible future events. Have the demographic
changes induced by AIDS in some African countries had a “positive” as well as a
“negative” influence on average income?
We do not know. What we do
know is that AIDS not only increases the death rate but also reduces the birth
rate. Where life expectancy has fallen - in several African countries
- it seems odd that any system claiming
to measure aggregate welfare outcomes would ignore Bentham’s obvious point that
more time doing something nice is better.
Since most people, even poor people, choose to stay alive, it is
rational to conclude that they find the prospect of living better than that of
dying. Where life length falls, to an equal extent at different income
levels, the average income gains to people during the period are less than
otherwise. It cannot be logical for a
system of counting consequences to people to ignore life length. The problem is, though, for those who
would calculate welfare, that the value of life is not measurable
objectively. It is not a matter of
social science, but a matter of philosophy.
There is no objective answer to the question of how much your life is
worth.
Cross-sectional statistics include measures claiming to show the degree of
inequality. These are also influenced
by demographic change. Standard measures
of inequality do not satisfy the Pigou-Dalton transfer principle. Whether an outcome is Paretian is not
knowable from static measures of welfare.
The question about the difference between [the change in the average] and [the average
gain or loss] is a fundamental theoretical issue, not an empirical one. It is an issue of economists recognising
what the word “utility” means, and not confusing averagism with utilitarianism. Averagism is only one form of
cross-sectionalism: the use of
statistics about living people at different times to infer gains or losses to
real people in the aggregate during a period. The gains and losses are longitudinal statistics: they are about the life courses of real
people.
Another problem in
economics is this: most economists
think that “if the proportion of
poor people in poor countries goes down, and certain other conditions are met such as that the depth of
poverty among living people did not get worse, then poor people got richer”. This doesn’t follow, because birth and
death rates may have changed. (In
relation to the proportion of poor people, some people may have crossed the
poverty line upwards while the majority had losses which were greater [9]).
I personally regard
all this as good: it means that
economists have been over-pessimistic about income gains to people where
demographic changes have been in particular directions. The task of finding out what the average
consequences for individuals were is not as simple as many economists (and most
governments) say, but then life is complex.
How much better people have done if they live longer is necessarily a
matter, as I said, of opinion. For a social scientist to develop a measure of welfare and then to use it is not the same thing as to have measured welfare. Why not?
Because the measure is necessarily subjective. Even if we could
measure static welfare levels of people
- which is perhaps more the
realm of the psychologist than the student of financial transactions - what weight would we choose to give to a year’s
extra life to a baby, or to a great-grandfather? One way to look at
economic success might be to look at lifetime income. This is certainly more
sane than using measures which look better if people in the majority die. But this would value a year of a poor
person’s life as less than a year of a rich person’s life, thus getting into a
similar problem which we were trying to avoid in the first place. And we are still left with trying to
compare more money during people’s lives (both yours while you are alive and
others’ lives while they are alive) with more life. If someone has the equation for this, then they are not
human. And we still would not have
tackled the relationships between income and purchasing power, purchasing power
and economic gains, or economic gains and well-being. The problem with the
practice of “welfare economics” seems to be that anything is OK as long as it’s
conventional. It doesn’t matter if
there is theory behind it or not, and it doesn’t matter if there are no
data. There are data suggesting that
people in Japan haven’t got happier just because they’ve got richer. This kind of thing is exactly what a
scientist would look at if they were trying to measure variable x
(income) and then use those statistics to make some statement about variable y (well-being).
The only thing which is rational to say about a social scientist’s measure of
welfare is that this measure has gone up or down. If people have slight income
falls in general (which is not the same as saying that the average fell!) but
poor people live much longer, there is no objective way of deciding whether the
outcome was on average better or worse.
Bentham wisely avoided this question.
My own simple
solution in the case of people who are poor in an absolute sense is to look at
survival rates. Whatever we look at in
terms of static measures of welfare, more of a good thing is always better for
the individual - there is more utility to the individual from
being alive longer. Longevity is
correlated with most things which we think are valuable. And it has little, if any, effect of
diminishing marginal returns.[10]
[1] I say “substantially” because some economic theorists (e.g. Samuelson) have discussed the use of lifetime income as a measure of economic success. Welfare economics is in practice overwhelmingly dominated by the idea that higher average income in a later population shows better consequences on average to real people, in exact proportion to the change in average income. I therefore refer to this perspective here as “economics” for reasons of brevity.
[2] The philosopher Thomas Hurka identified eleven in two articles in the journal Analysis in 1982.
[3] Described as absurd by the philosopher Derek Parfit in 1986 (in Applied Ethics, edited by Peter Singer).
[4] Except of course for the situation where someone is in the position of choosing to create more people.
[5] In the case
of income or consumption statistics, there is a further hurdle for the
averagist.
Since we do not expect children to have the same income or consumption as
adults, per capita statistics which jumble up adults and children do not
fundamentally measure how well- or badly- off people are.
Again, the necessary condition is that the ratio of children to adults does not
change; more technically, that the age
structure does not change. The age
structure is also influenced by the ratio of older people (see note 7 on
retired people below).
[6][6] This is a common criticism of averagism.
[7] Not “poor people”, but as I have said, most
people.
Where I say “live longer” I mean “go on living”, not “live to a greater age
eventually”. In other words, I am
talking about people at any age continuing to stay alive. In
relation to retired people, who typically have lower incomes than most adults,
the vast majority of them will raise the average by dying and lower it by
continuing to live.
[8] Except in relation to some statistics about China and East Asian countries. There is as far as I know no synthesis of such results for the purposes of estimating income gains in other countries, or devising a rational framework for economists to use in estimating income gains generally.
[9] Sen has said what I say in (b), in
essence; but economists and
statisticians regularly ignore it.
Official statements on world poverty from the UK government and the UN,
based on conclusions from the World Bank, do ignore it.
[10] I discuss this, as well as other solutions
and other logical problems in economics, in my book-length document The
Wealth of Persons: Ambiguities and
assumptions in the foundations of economics, and how to resolve them. I suspect that this will end up as several publications.